musicbutton





 

 

 

Time and its role in the history of thought and action

 

Abstract:

This article discusses the history of thought about Time distinguishing process-philosophers and philosopers of the manifold, philosphers of everlasting life and philosophers of rebirth in the flow of time. The prescietific conception of the individual experience of reality to time and timelessness is pictured as a ground for the division between holders of the cyclic view and holders of the one-way view of time. Despite of the original Western religious one way concept, the cyclic aspect of time has , this article maintains, gained adherents. With the Greeks the alternating between love and strife (our Ying & Yang) opposing the denial of motion and plurality suggested the flow of time as the essence of reality. Christian one-way thinking is thereto recognized as apocalyptic leading to crisis and collapse also described in modern social theory. Modern scientific concepts are described as making systems remaining constant through time, leading to another kind of metaphysics.

taken from the Encyclopedia Britannica ( on the Net since 19 0kt '99)

Unfortunately Brittanica has closed theis services for free use. Therefore the links in this article run dead. Someday we will have the knowledge liberated!!(see filognostic revolution)

 

Introduction

Time: a measured or measurable period, a continuum that lacks spatial dimensions. Time is of philosophical interest and is also the subject of mathematical and scientific investigation. (See time.)

 

Time and its role in the history of thought and action

 

Introduction

Time and its role in the history of thought and action

Nature and definition of time

Prescientific conceptions of time and their influence

The individual's experience and observation of time

Cyclic view of time in the philosophy of history

Environmental recurrences and religion

The cyclic view in various cultures

One-way view of time in the philosophy of history

Early modern and 19th-century scientific philosophies of time

 

 

Nature and definition of time

Time appears to be more puzzling than space because it seems to flow or pass or else people seem to advance through it. But the passage or advance seems to be unintelligible. The question of how many seconds per second time flows (or one advances through it) is obviously an absurd one, for it suggests that the flow or advance comprises a rate of change with respect to something else--to a sort of hypertime. But if this hypertime itself flows, then a hyper-hypertime is required, and so on, ad infinitum. Again, if the world is thought of as spread out in space-time, it might be asked whether human consciousness advances up a timelike direction of this world and, if so, how fast; whether future events pop into existence as the "now" reaches them or are there all along; and how such changes in space-time can be represented, since time is already within the picture. (Ordinary change can, of course, be represented in a space-time picture: for example, a particle at rest is represented by a straight line and an oscillating particle by a wavy line.) (See metaphysics, process philosophy.)

In the face of these difficulties, philosophers tend to divide into two sorts: the "process philosophers" and the "philosophers of the manifold." Process philosophers--such as A. N. W., an Anglo-American metaphysician who died in 1947--hold that the flow of time (or human advance through it) is an important metaphysical fact. Like the French intuitionist H. B., they may hold that this flow can be grasped only by nonrational intuition. Bergson even held that the scientific concept of time as a dimension actually misrepresents reality. Philosophers of the manifold hold that the flow of time or human advance through time is an illusion. They argue, for example, that words such as past, future, and now, as well as the tenses of verbs, are indexical expressions that refer to the act of their own utterance. Hence, the alleged change of an event from being future to being past is an illusion. To say that the event is future is to assert that it is later than this utterance; then later yet, when one says that it is in the past, he or she asserts that it is earlier than that other utterance. Past and future are not real predicates of events in this view; and change in respect of them is not a genuine change. (See W., A. N., B., H. )

Again, although process philosophers think of the future as somehow open or indeterminate, whereas the past is unchangeable, fixed, determinate, philosophers of the manifold hold that it is as much nonsense to talk of changing the future as it is to talk of changing the past. If a person decides to point left rather than to point right, then pointing left is what the future was. Moreover, this thesis of the determinateness of the future, they argue, must not be confused with determinism, the theory that there are laws whereby later states of the universe may be deduced from earlier states (or vice versa). The philosophy of the manifold is neutral about this issue. Future events may well exist and yet not be connected in a sufficiently lawlike way with earlier ones. (See determinism.)

One of the features of time that puzzled the Platonist A., in the 5th century AD, was the difficulty of defining it. In contemporary philosophy of language, however (influenced by L. W., a Cambridge philosopher), no mystery is seen in this task. Learning to handle the word time involves a multiplicity of verbal skills, including the ability to handle such connected words as earlier, later, now, second, and hour. These verbal skills have to be picked up in very complex ways (partly by ostension), and it is not surprising that the meaning of the word time cannot be distilled into a neat verbal definition. (It is not, for example, an abbreviating word like bachelor.) (See analytic proposition.)

The philosophy of time bears powerfully on human emotions. Not only do individuals regret the past, they also fear the future, not least because the alleged flow of time seems to be sweeping them toward their deaths, as swimmers are swept toward a waterfall.
(See
death.)

 

Prescientific conceptions of time and their influence

 

The individual's experience and observation of time

The irreversibility and inexorability of the passage of time is borne in on human beings by the fact of death. Unlike other living creatures, they know that their lives may be cut short at any moment and that, even if they attain the full expectation of human life, their growth is bound to be followed by eventual decay and, in due time, death (see also time perception).

Although there is no generally accepted evidence that death is not the conclusive end of life, it is a tenet of some religions (e.g., of Zoroastrianism, Judaism, Christianity, and Islam) that death is followed by everlasting life elsewhere--in sheol, hell, or heaven--and that eventually there will be a universal physical resurrection. Others (e.g., Buddhists, Orphics, Pythagoreans, and P.) have held that people are reborn in the time flow of life on Earth and that the notion that a human being has only one life on Earth is the illusion of a lost memory. The Buddha claimed to recollect all of his previous lives. The Greek philosophers P. and E., of the 6th and early 5th centuries BC, whose lives probably overlapped that of the B., likewise claimed to recollect some of their previous lives. Such rebirths, they held, would continue to recur unless a person should succeed in breaking the vicious circle (releasing himself from the "sorrowful wheel") by strenuous ascetic performances. (See afterlife, reincarnation, B., P., E., Buddhism, Platonism.)

The belief that a person's life in time on Earth is repetitive may have been an inference from the observed repetitiveness of phenomena in the environment. The day-and-night cycle and the annual cycle of the seasons dominated the conduct of human life until the recent harnessing of inanimate physical forces in the Industrial Revolution made it possible for work to be carried on for 24 hours a day throughout the year--under cover, by artificial light, and at a controlled temperature. There is also the generation cycle, which the Industrial Revolution has not suppressed: the generations still replace each other, in spite of the lengthening of life expectancies. In some societies it has been customary to give a man's son a different name but to give his grandson the same name. To name father and son differently is an admission that generations change; but to name grandfather and grandson the same is perhaps an intimation that the grandson is the grandfather reincarnate. (See cyclicism, season, Industrial Revolution.)

Thus, though every human being has the experience of irreversible change in his own life, he also observes cyclic change in his environment; hence the adherents of some religions and philosophies have inferred that, despite appearances, time flows cyclically for the individual human being, too.

The human experience and observation of time has been variously interpreted. P., an Italiote Greek ( Eleatic) philosopher (6th-5th century BC) and Z., his fellow townsman and disciple, held that change is logically inconceivable and that logic is a surer indicator of reality than experience; thus, despite appearances, reality is unitary and motionless. In this view, time is an illusion. The illusoriness of the world that "flows" in time is also to be found in some Indian philosophy. The B. and, among the Greeks, P. and P., all held that life in the time flow, though not wholly illusory, is at best a low-grade condition by comparison, respectively, with the Buddhist Nirvana (in which desires are extinguished) and with the Platonic world of Ideas; i.e., of incorporeal timeless exemplars, of which phenomena in the time flow are imperfect and ephemeral copies. (See P., Eleaticism, Z. of E., P..)

It has been held, however--e.g., by disciples of the Greek philosopher H.--that the time flow is of the essence of reality. Others have held that life in the time flow, though it may be wretched, is nevertheless momentous; for it is here that a person decides his destiny. In the Buddhist view, a person's conduct in any one of his successive lives on Earth will increase or diminish his prospects of eventually breaking out of the cycle of recurrent births. For those who believe in only one earthly life, however, the momentousness of life in the time flow is still greater because this life will be followed by an everlasting life at a destination decided by conduct in this brief and painful testing time. The view that life in time on Earth is a probation for weal or woe in an everlasting future has often been associated--as it was by the Iranian prophet Z. (c. 600 BC)--with a belief in a general judgment of all who have ever lived to be held on a common judgment day, which will be the end of time. The belief in an immediate individual judgment was also held in pharaonic Egypt. Both of these beliefs have been adopted by Jews, Christians, and Muslims. (See H., Z., Z..)

Cyclic view of time in the philosophy of history

The foregoing diverse interpretations of the nature and significance of the individual human being's experience and observation of time differ sharply from each other, and they have led to equally sharp differences in views of human history and of ultimate reality and in prescriptions for the conduct, both collective and individual, of human life. Thinkers have been divided between holders of the cyclic view and holders of the one-way view of time and between believers in the different prescriptions for the conduct of life that these differing views have suggested. Variations in the two basic views of time and in the corresponding codes of conduct have been among the salient characteristics distinguishing the principal civilizations and philosophies and higher religions that have appeared in history to date. (See history, philosophy of.)

Environmental recurrences and religion

The cyclic theory of time has been held in regard to the three fields of religion, of history (both human and cosmic), and of personal life. That this view arose from the observation of recurrences in the environment is most conspicuously seen in the field of religion. The observation of the generation cycle has been reflected in the cult of ancestors, important in Chinese religion and also in older civilizations and in precivilizational societies. The observation of the annual cycle of the seasons and its crucial effect on agriculture is reflected in a ceremony in which the emperor of China used to plow the first furrow of the current year; in the ceremonial opening of a breach in the dike of the Nile to let the annual floodwaters irrigate the land; and in the annual "sacred marriage," performed by a priest and priestess representing a god and goddess, which was deemed to ensure the continuing fertility of Babylonia. A cycle longer than that of the seasons is represented by the recurrent avataras (epiphanies, incarnate, on Earth) of the Hindu god V. (V.) and in the corresponding series of buddhas and bodhisattvas (potential buddhas). Although the only historical B. was S. G. (6th-5th century BC), in the mythology of the northern school of Buddhism (the Mahayana), the identity of the historical B. has been almost effaced by a long vista of putative buddhas extending through previous and future times. (See ancestor worship, Chinese religion, Hinduism, Mahayana.)

In contrast to northern Buddhism and to Vaisnava Hinduism, Christianity holds that the incarnation of God in J. was a unique event; yet the rite of the Eucharist, in which C.'s self-sacrifice is held by Catholic and Eastern Orthodox Christians to be reperformed, is celebrated every day by thousands of priests, and the nature of this rite has suggested to some scholars that it originated in an annual festival at the culmination of the agricultural year. In this interpretation, the bread that is C.'s body and the wine that is his blood associate him with the annually dying gods A., O., and A.--the divinities, inherent in the vital and vitalizing power of the crops, who die in order that people may eat and drink and live. "Unless a grain of wheat falls into the earth and dies, it remains alone; but, if it dies, it bears much fruit" (John 12:24).(See Christianity, Eucharist.)

 

The cyclic view in various cultures

The cyclic view of history, both cosmic and human, has been prevalent among the Hindus and the pre-Christian Greeks, the Chinese, and the Aztecs. More recently, the cyclic view has gained adherents in modern Western society, although this civilization was originally Christian--that is, was nurtured on a religion that sees time as a one-way flow and not as a cyclic one.

The Chinese, Hindus, and Greeks saw cosmic time as moving in an alternating rhythm, classically expressed in the Chinese concept of the alternation between Yin, the passive female principle, and Yang, the dynamic male principle. When either Yin or Yang goes to extremes, it overlaps the other principle, which is its correlative and complement in consequence of being its opposite. In the philosophy of E., an early Greek thinker, the equivalents of Yin and Yang were Love and Strife. E. revolted against the denial of the reality of motion and plurality that was made by his Eleatic predecessors on the strength of mere logic. He broke up the Eleatics' motionless, and therefore timeless, unitary reality into a movement of four elements that were alternately harmonized by Love and set at variance by Strife. E. Love and Strife, like Yin and Yang, each overlapped the other when they had gone to extremes. (See yin-yang, E., E., Eleaticism.)

 

One-way view of time in the philosophy of history

When the flow of time is held to be not recurrent but one-way, it can be conceived of as having a beginning and perhaps an end. Some thinkers have felt that such limits can be imagined only if there is some timeless power that has set time going and intends or is set to stop it. A god who creates and then annihilates time, if he is held to be omnipotent, is often credited with having done this with a benevolent purpose that is being carried out according to plan. The omnipotent god's plan, in this view, governs the time flow and is made manifest to humans in progressive revelations through the prophets--from A., by way of M, I., and J., to the Prophet M.(as Muslims believe). (See Providence.)

This belief in Heilsgeschichte (salvational history) has been derived by Islam and Christianity from Judaism and Zoroastrianism. Late in the 12th century, the Christian seer J. of F. saw this divinely ordained spiritual progress in the time flow as unfolding in a series of three ages--those of the Father, the Son, and the Spirit. K. J., a 20th-century Western philosopher, has discerned an "axis age"--i.e., a turning point in human history--in the 6th century BC, when C., the B., Z, D.-I., and P. were alive contemporaneously. If the "axis age" is extended backward in time to the original I's generation and forward to M.'s, it may perhaps be recognized as the age in which humans first sought to make direct contact with the ultimate spiritual reality behind phenomena instead of making such communication only indirectly through their nonhuman and social environments. (See salvation, J. of F., J., K. T.r.)

The belief in an omnipotent creator god, however, has been challenged. The creation of time, or of anything else, out of nothing is difficult to imagine; and, if God is not a creator but is merely a shaper, his power is limited by the intractability of the independent material with which he has had to work. P, in the Timaeus, conceived of God as being a nonomnipotent shaper and thus accounted for the manifest element of evil in phenomena. M., a 2nd-century Christian heretic, inferred from the evil in phenomena that the creator was bad and held that a "stranger god" had come to redeem the bad creator's work at the benevolent stranger's cost. Z. saw the phenomenal world as a battlefield between a bad god and a good one and saw time as the duration of this battle. Though he held that the good god was destined to be the victor, a god who needs to fight and win is not omnipotent. In an attenuated form, this evil adversary appears in the three Judaic religions as Satan. (See "Timaeus", M. of P., evil, problem of, Z..)

Observation of historical phenomena suggests that, in spite of the manifestness of evil, there has been progress in the history of life on this planet, culminating in the emergence of humans who know themselves to be sinners yet feel themselves to be something better than inanimate matter. C. D., in his theory of the selection of mutations by the environment, sought to vindicate apparent progress in the organic realm without recourse to an extraneous god. In the history of Greek thought, the counterpart of such mutations was the swerving of atoms. After E. had broken up the indivisible, motionless, and timeless reality of P. and Z. into four elements played upon alternately by Love and Strife, it was a short step for the Atomists of the 5th century BC, L. and D., to break up reality still further into an innumerable host of minute atoms moving in time through a vacuum. Granting that one single atom had once made a single slight swerve, the build-up of observed phenomena could be accounted for on Darwinian lines. D.' account of evolution survives in the fifth book of De rerum natura, written by a 1st-century-BC Roman poet, L.. The credibility of both D.' and D.'s accounts of evolution depends on the assumption that time is real and that its flow has been extraordinarily long. (See D., C. R., natural selection, atomism, L., D., "On the Nature of Things,".)

H. had seen in phenomena a harmony of opposites in tension with each other and had concluded that War (i.e., E.' Strife and the Chinese Yang) "is father of all and king of all." This vision of Strife as being the dominant and creative force is grimmer than that of Strife alternating on equal terms with Love and Yang with Yin. In the 19th-century West, H.' vision has been revived in the view of G.W.F. H., a German Idealist, that progress occurs through a synthesis resulting from an encounter between a thesis and an antithesis. In political terms, H.' vision has reappeared in K. M.'s concept of an encounter between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat and the emergence of a classless society without a government. (See H., Hegel, G. W. F., M..)

In the Zoroastrian and Jewish-Christian-Islamic vision of the time flow, time is destined to be consummated--as depicted luridly in the Revelation to John--in a terrifying climax. It has become apparent that history has been accelerating, and accumulated knowledge of the past has revealed, in retrospect, that the acceleration began about 30,000 years ago, with the transition from the Lower to the Upper Paleolithic Period, and that it has taken successive "great leaps forward" with the invention of agriculture, with the dawn of civilization, and with the progressive harnessing--within the last two centuries--of the titanic physical forces of inanimate nature. The approach of the climax foreseen intuitively by the prophets is being felt, and feared, as a coming event. Its imminence is, today, not an article of faith but a datum of observation and experience.(A.J.T.) (See apocalypticism.)

 

Early modern and 19th-century scientific philosophies of time

I. N. distinguished absolute time from "relative, apparent, and common time" as measured by the apparent motions of the fixed stars, as well as by terrestrial clocks. His absolute time was an ideal scale of time that made the laws of mechanics simpler, and its discrepancy with apparent time was attributed to such things as irregularities in the motion of the Earth. Insofar as these motions were explained by N.'s mechanics (or at least could not be shown to be inexplicable), the procedure was vindicated. Similarly, in his notion of absolute space, Newton was really getting at the concept of an inertial system. Nevertheless, the notion of space and time as absolute metaphysical entities was encouraged by Newton's views and formed an important part of the philosophy of I. K., a German critical philosopher, for whom space and time were "phenomenally real" (part of the world as described by science) but "noumenally unreal" (not a part of the unknowable world of things in themselves). K. argued for the noumenal unreality of space and time on the basis of certain antinomies that he claimed to find in these notions--that the universe had a beginning, for example, and yet (by another argument) could not have had a beginning. In a letter dated 1798, he wrote that the antinomies had been instrumental in arousing him from his "dogmatic slumber" (pre-critical philosophy). Modern advances in logic and mathematics, however, have convinced most philosophers that the antinomies contain fallacies. (See N., Sir I., celestial mechanics, classical mechanics, K., I., antinomy.)

Newtonian mechanics, as studied in the 18th century, was mostly concerned with periodic systems that, on a large scale, remain constant throughout time. Particularly notable was the proof of the stability of the solar system that was formulated by P.-S., marquis de L., a mathematical astronomer. Interest in systems that develop through time came about in the 19th century as a result of the theories of the British geologist Sir C. L., and others, and the Darwinian theory of evolution. These theories led to a number of biologically inspired metaphysical systems, which were often--as with H. B. and A N W--rather romantic and contrary to the essentially mechanistic spirit of D. himself (and also of present-day molecular biology).

(See L., P.-S., m.de.)/

 

Search for related Internet links that use the term "time".

 

 

 

 

back to Time Sciences          

 
 

back to science-main         


 
©2001 theorderoftime.com